Inheritance in Socio‐Political Context: The Case for Reviving the Sociological Discourse of Inheritance Tax Law

DOIhttp://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6478.2007.00405.x
Published date01 December 2007
AuthorAnn Mumford
Date01 December 2007
JOURNAL OF LAW AND SOCIETY
VOLUME 34, NUMBER 4, DECEMBER 2007
ISSN: 0263-323X, pp. 567±93
Inheritance in Socio-Political Context:
The Case for Reviving the Sociological
Discourse of Inheritance Tax Law
Ann Mumford*
The anti-`death tax' movement is the starting point for contemporary
discussions of inheritance taxation. The political rhetoric surrounding
calls for its repeal typically is met with analyses of the extent to which
inheritance tax avoidance benefits the wealthy, and arguments that
inheritance taxation is fair and `targeted'. This article suggests that
engagement by tax lawyers with sociological theories of economic
inheritance has the potential to revive this discourse. A renewed
approach to inheritance taxation is of immediate concern to
supporters of inheritance taxation in the United Kingdom, who face
considerable obstacles posed by the increasing use of United States
anti-inheritance tax movement political rhetoric by politicians.
Durkheim's consideration of the conjugal family and, more recently,
Beckert's sociology of inheritance are submitted as analyses that,
amongst others, have particular potential. Such engagement also has
the potential to revive the interest of sociologists in inheritance
taxation, memorably described by MacNamee an d Miller as a
`sociological lacuna.'
INTRODUCTION: THE VICTIM IS DEAD
Within limits, no economist will question the propriety of laying taxes on
bequests and inheritances. They are collected with ease and reasonable
certainty. They fall upon something which the taxpayer has never yet enjoyed
and the diminution of which he therefore does not fully miss. The goose, to
follow Colbert's maxim, is plucked so as to get the most feathers with the least
567
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School. Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd,
9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA
*Queen Mary University, Mile End Road, London E1 4NS, England
a.c.mumford@qmul.ac.uk
The author wishes to thank the anonymous referees for this journal for their invaluable
assistance.
squealing, and almost with none. Live goose feathers, indeed, are not required.
The real victim is dead.
1
In 1905, Simeon Baldwin argued that the case for inheritance taxation is
simple. As long society agrees that some form of taxation is necessary to
fund government, then inheritance taxation should be one of the least
controversial forms of tax assessment and collection. `The real victim is
dead', as Baldwin suggested, and therefore not in a position to protest.
2
Supporters of inheritance tax would view this suggestion nostalgically, for
much has changed. Essentially, opposing inheritance taxation appears to be
popular amongst voters,
3
and analyses have paused to grapple with this
difficulty.
4
A revival of this discussion may be enhanced through engage-
ment between sociologists and tax legal theorists, who, together, could
reclaim the discourse of inheritance tax law.
This article does not suggest that inheritance tax in the United Kingdom is
in any immediate danger. The efforts of, for example, Stephen Byers, have
decreased in political significance, and there is little possibility of the anti-
inheritance tax platform of the United Kingdom Independence Party
5
finding
its way to Downing Street. Perhaps most importantly, the Prime Minister
made his support for inheritance taxation clear during his tenure as Chan-
cellor of the Exchequer.
6
Nonetheless, this article submits that an informed
568
1S.Baldwin, `The Modern ``Droit D'Aubaine''' (1905) 14 Yale Law J. 129±47, at
133. Simeon Baldwin was a professor at Yale Law School, and later governor of
Connecticut.
2 id.
3 Seemingly across geographical boundaries: see A. Massone and C. Massone,
``Should the death tax die? And should it leave an inheritance?' at
econpapers.repec.org/paper/ucaucapdv/22.htm>; see, also, L.M. Bartels, `Homer
Gets a Tax Cut: Inequality and Public Policy in the American Mind' (2005) 3
Perspectives on Politics 15; M. Birney and I. Shapiro, `The Political Uses of Public
Opinion: Lessons from the Estate Tax Repeal' (2005) at
polisci/info/conferences/DistributivePolitics/papers/Birney%20_Shapiro.pdf>; M.A.
Smith, (review article) `Does Business Learn?: Tax Breaks, Uncertainty, and
Political Strategies. By Sandra L. Suarez' (2005) 95 American Political Science
Rev. 487. But things may be changing: see A.D. Postal, `Senate Votes show repeal
of estate taxes is losing steam' National Underwriter/Life & Health Financial
Services,4February 2007, 6±33.
4 See D.W. Matthews, `A Fight to the Death: Slaying the Estate Tax Repeal Hydra'
(2006) 28 Whittier Law Rev. 663; R. Safford, `Information Asymmetry, Race, and
the ``Death Tax'' ' (2006) 13 Washington and Lee J. of Civil Rights and Social
Justice 117; and E.J. McCaffery and L.R. Cohen, `Shakedown at Gucci Gulch: The
New Logic of Collective Action' (2006) 84 North Carolina Law Rev. 1159.
5UKIP's anti-inheritance tax platform is at
ukipflattaxpolicy.pdf>.
6 The strongest evidence of this is his last Budget Speech,
treasury.gov.uk/budget/budget_07/bud_bud07_speech.cfm>. This article went to
press before Alistair Darling's pre-Budget report on 10 October 2007. Nonetheless,
the arguments within this article are strengthened by these recent developments in
inheritance tax law.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
dialogue on the propriety of inheritance taxation is of immediate importance
to supporters of an inheritance tax, and as a response to the `anti-death tax'
movement.
7
Sociologists and tax lawyers have seldom discussed economic
inheritance.
8
This article will place inheritance tax within standard
sociological discourse of economic inheritance.
The article will trace the twentieth-century evolution of the United
Kingdom's inheritance tax from the darling of economists, to the bane of
populists. What happened to inheritance taxation in the United States, and
why it matters in the United Kingdom, will be explained.
9
Inheritance
taxation is an emotive topic, with uncertain political fortunes. Traditional
economic arguments concerning inheritance taxation, such as economic
efficiency, progressivity, and fairness (especially in light of conflicts con-
cerning the rising value of the family home) will be placed in context. The
objective is to place inheritance tax within the context of sociological theories
of economic redistribution. The significance of the language used to describe
inheritance taxation (whether `death taxes', `estate taxes' or `inheritance
taxes') will be considered. The conflicts that arise over the treatment of `adult
children' also will be addressed. This article will not suggest that taxpayers
will ever happily pay any tax, never mind inheritance tax, but it will attempt
to challenge assumptions found in inheritance tax debate.
PROPOSED TARGET OF SOCIOLOGICAL INQUIRY:
INHERITANCE TAX LAW IN THE UNITED KINGDOM
From an economic perspective, perhaps it is surprising that inheritance
taxation is controversial. Imposition on the wealth of dead people should
lessen the amount that is needed from living taxpayers. Dead taxpayers will
not hire advisers to help them avoid their obligations, and will not complain
569
7 There is `a small but growing number of developed countries in which taxes on the
transfer of wealth have been abolished': D.G. Duff, `The Abolition of Wealth
Transfer Taxes: Lessons from Canada, Australia, and New Zealand' (2005) 3
Pittsburgh Tax Rev. 1.
8
As opposed to the vibrant discourse on cultural inheritance. Reviews of this vast
literature include: A. Portes, `Social Capital: Its Origins and Applications in Modern
Sociology' (1998) 24 Annual Rev. of Sociology 1; R. Boyd and P.J. Richerson, Culture
and the Evolutionary Process (1988); M. Egerton, `Occupational Inheritance: The Role
of Cultural Capital and Gender' (1997) 11 Work, Employment and Society 263.
Amongst the leading theorists (discussed in these works) who consider cultural
inheritance are Durkheim (for example, E. Durkheim and R.N. Bellah, E
Âmile Durkheim
on Morality and Society: Selected Writings (1973)) and Giddens (for example, A.
Giddens, The Constitution of Society: Outline of Theory of Structuration (1986)).
9 Although a recent vote in the US Senate (Postal, op. cit., n. 3) may indicate that the
prospects of the estate tax are stronger there than writers such as Graetz and Shapiro
fear. M.J. Graetz and I. Shapiro, Death by a Thousand Cuts: The Fight Over Taxing
Inherited Wealth (2005), especially ch. 9.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
about the intrusion of Revenue in their affairs. The impact upon dead
taxpayers of the taxes collected should be minimal.
The beneficiaries of dead taxpayers may not view such taxation as
blithely as Simeon Baldwin, but they might be viewed as unlikely to pose too
much of a problem. Beneficiaries also are lucky people, as they inherit
money and assets which they, personally, may not have earned. The taxman
may interfere with this, but, essentially, their good fortune remains. Any
strong degree of protest might be viewed, politically, as unimportant.
The political reality at present, however, is quite different. Decried as the
most unfair of all taxes, inheritance taxes have been denounced as little
better than attempts to confiscate property from grieving relatives.
10
The
current United Kingdom repeal movement was inspired by the striking
abolition of the federal inheritance tax in the United States, which was the
fulfilment of a promise made by George W. Bush during the 2000
presidential election campaign, and is also only temporary. As the issue will
be considered again in 2010,
11
the rhetoric to keep the `unfair' and `un-
American' tax at bay is heated. The reaction of United States tax law
scholars has been led Graetz and Shapiro, who have expressed surprise at
this turn of events.
12
Tax scholars are starting to show interest in the change
in political scene for inheritance tax in the United Kingdom,
13
which Tiley
has described as involving a `much more determined agenda'.
14
In the United States, the inheritance tax affected only a small proportion of
the overall population, and yet a majority of the population strongly supported
its repeal.
15
That the inheritance tax should be so unpopular, thus, did not
appear to be rational, yet its repeal provided a great deal of political capital for
Republican politicians.
16
Efforts to abolish the inheritance tax in the United
Kingdom perhaps are motivated by similar ambitions for political reward.
A sociological discourse on inheritance taxation promises to move beyond
politics, and past subjects of fairness, avoidance, and politics, which are the
standard concerns of tax legal theory. It offers reconsideration of the value of
inherited property, but also (through Durkheim, and, to some extent, Marx)
acknowledgment of the relationships that build between people in the
creation of wealth ± a point with much potential on the subject of the `family
570
10 S. Byers, `Next Labour PM Must Abolish Inheritance Tax' Daily Telegraph,20
August 2006.
11 See Economic Growth and Tax Relief Reconciliation Act of 2001.
12 See Graetz and Shapiro, op. cit., n. 9.
13 See C. Pratten, `Gordon Brown Counts Dead Children: The True Impact of
Inheritance Tax' (2006) 26 Economic Affairs 74; Duff, op. cit., n. 7, at p..48, fn. 318;
and, Massone et al., op. cit., n. 3.
14 J. Tiley, `Death and Taxes' (2007) Brit. Tax Rev. 300±19, at 319.
15 See Graetz and Shapiro, op. cit., n. 9, at pp. 3±11, discussing `A Political Mystery'.
Only 6 per cent of estates pay inheritance tax in the United Kingdom: Pratten, op.
cit., n. 13.
16 `Genesis of the Repeal Coalition', Graetz and Shapiro, id., at pp. 12±23.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
home.' Finally, it provides a link between theories of inequality and different
forms of inherited wealth.
17
This section will provide an introduction to the material with which the
theories would need to work: inheritance tax law in the United Kingdom. On
the one hand, the subject is relatively straightforward. Inheritance tax is
intended to tax transfers of wealth at, or shortly before, death.
18
Transfers
which fall below a minimum threshold will not be taxed.
19
Inheritance tax is
levied on amounts which exceed this threshold, and at a rate of 40 per cent
for transfers made up to three years before death, and for those made after
death.
20
As a general rule, if transfers of wealth occur between three and
seven years before death, they will be taxed at a reduced rate.
21
If transfers
are made more than seven years before death, they will not be taxed.
22
Transfers between spouses and civil partners, and to political parties and
charities are exempt from inheritance tax.
23
Assets associated with small
businesses and farms may receive relief, achieved by reducing the value of
the asset between 50 per cent and 100 per cent.
24
On the other hand, however, inheritance tax law has a very long history in
the United Kingdom (even pre-dating the Union), and is difficult to
summarize succinctly. Indeed, some form of inheritance taxation has been
traced back to 2000 BC.
25
As Carrington wrote in 1920:
Death duties had their origin perhaps in ancient Egypt. They were imposed in
Rome under the Emperor Augustus, and have been more or less constantly
571
17 See the analyses in C.D. Harbury and D.M.W.N. Hitchens, Inheritance and Wealth
Inequality in Britain (1979). From a study of patterns of inheritance by wealthy
British sons, Harbury and Hitchens drew the conclusion that restrictions upon
bequests were likely to have an ameliorative impact upon economic inequality. This
study was widely influential, and was described by Sandford as providing a `. . .
quanitif[ication] of the importance of inheritance in the distribution of wealth.' (C.
Sandford, `Review (1980) 90 Economic J. 674.)
18 S. Adam and J. Browne, A Survey of the United Kingdom Tax System (2006) 16±17.
19 Finance Act 2006, pt. VI, s. 155 provides the rates and rate bands for 2008±2009
(£312,000) and 2009±2010 (£325,000). The 2007 Budget set the limit for 2010±
2011 at £350,000.
20 Adam and Browne, op. cit., n. 18. See Inheritance Tax Act 1984, ch. 51.
21 See Inheritance Tax Act 1984, ch. 51, s. 7 (hereafter, IHTA 1984).
22 id.
23 id., at s. 18. The United Kingdom government recently was challenged in the
European Court of Human Rights in the case of Burden & Anor v. United Kingdom
(2007) 44 EHRR 51, on the question of whether cohabiting sisters should receive the
same inheritance tax exemptions as spouses and civil partners. The Court held that it
was reasonable to deny the sisters this exemption, and accepted the United
Kingdom's contention that the exemption was designed to promote family stability
between spouses and civil partners, exclusively.
24 IHTA 1984, s. 16.
25 M.H. Hunter, `The Inheritance Tax' (1921) Annals of the Am. Academy of Political
and Social Science 165±80, at 165.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
recognised as a proper source of revenue of all civilised nations in one form or
another, ever since that time.
26
Additionally, this history is not untroubled, and indeed there are various
moments of historic controversy revealing the sensitivity of such a tax. Two
examples, in particular, are relevant to this paper.
First, in 1796, Pitt and others worried that a tax on property might inter-
fere with the right to own land.
27
Taxes on death, nonetheless, were common
during this era,
28
if not necessarily onerous.
29
In fact, Jenkins suggested that
there was `gross discrimination in favour of land'
30
under this system, and
amendments by Harcourt were designed to remedy this.
31
The amendments
were successful, such that, decades later, Victorian Britain relied heavily on
death duties, even during an era which history has celebrated more for its
development of the income tax.
32
Such reservations resurfaced a second time, more than two hundred years
later. The 1972 Green Paper,
33
proposed to assess tax on the amounts
received by beneficiaries, as opposed to the estate of a decedent.
34
The
advantage for the government, in terms of perception, was that only living
taxpayers would be taxed ± dead taxpayers would be completely out of the
picture.
35
The tax allowed consideration of the relationship between the
572
26 R.W. Carrington, `Death Duties' (1920) Virginia Law Rev. 568±79, at 568. Stewart
suggests that an association between inheritance taxation and `civilised nations' may
not have persisted, noting that Australia does not have an inheritance tax even
though it has `egalitarian credentials (albeit a little shaky)'. M. Stewart, `Taxes and
Justice in Context' (2005) 30 Aus. J. of Legal Philosophy 133±46, at 140; L. Murphy
and T. Nagel, The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice (2002).
27 M. Daunton, Trusting Leviathan: The Politics of Taxation in Britain 1799±1914
(2001) 226±7.
28 Daunton explains that, until Sir William Harcourt's Budget of 1894, four separate
and individual duties arose on death: `probate, legacy, succession and estate' , id., p.
225.
29 Roy Jenkins, The Chancellors (1999) 63.
30 id.
31 id. Harcourt feared resistance at the time, writing, `I have no doubt that we shall
have a ``formidable enemy'' in those who find themselves deprived of monopolies
they ought never to have possessed, and the privileges which enrich them at the
expense of their poorer fellows.' In the end, however, the resistance Harcourt faced
in 1894 from his fellow politicians never caught on with the populace, and the
Budget passed relatively easily.
32 See Daunton, op. cit., n. 27, ch. 8, pp. 224±55, explaining that the development of
the inheritance tax during this era is sometimes neglected, because of the extent to
which the income tax was developed and refined.
33 HM Treasury, Taxation of Capital on Death ± A Possible Inheritance Tax in place of
Estate Duty (1972; Cmnd. 4930).
34 S.M. Cretney, `An Inheritance Tax' (1973) 36 Modern Law Rev. 284, at 285.
35 Special Commissioners involved in the case of Holland explained, `[i]n that context
the phrase ``inheritance tax'' was used to describe a possible tax on beneficiaries
which in the event was not enacted.' Holland v. CIR [2003] STC (SCD) 43 (11
December 2002).
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
decedent and family members, a line of thought which probably lead to the
1975 Capital Transfer Tax's unlimited exemption for spousal transfers.
36
Contemplating these differences of treatment for familial relationships,
Cretney (in 1973) suggested that `[i]t is not clear what social objective would
be achieved.'
37
He wrote that such an arrangement would encourage wealth
to stay within families, and `. . . it is not clear why that is thought desir-
able.'
38
In any case, the 1975 Capital Transfer Tax was not successful, and
the modern inheritance tax was introduced as its successor.
39
Both events are interesting because they acknowledge reservations with
the constitutionality (from Pitt's perspective) and the target (from the
perspective of the Capital Transfer Tax) of inheritance taxation. As the paper
will argue, there is potential for consideration of both subjects within a
socio-legal discourse. Pitt's concerns have not survived, but the idea that
inheritance taxation interferes with property ownership in an improper way
has. Concerns about the perception of inheritance taxation, as perhaps an
attempt by the taxman to reach even into death, have survived. Indeed, they
have formed part of the modern discourse of the anti-`death tax' movement.
INHERITANCE TAXATION AND CONTROVERSY
The United Kingdom inheritance tax has avoided United States-style
repeal.
40
The Times explained that the anti-inheritance tax campaign has
received a great deal of attention in political circles because its cause has
been championed by Stephen Byers, who `is deemed in Westminster to
reflect the thoughts of Tony Blair.'
41
Writing of the previous Prime Minister,
the paper also suggested that, if Tony Blair in fact did support abolition of
the inheritance tax, then he would be following in the steps of another
(unsuccessful) supporter of its abolition, John Major.
42
Another former Labour Cabinet Minister, Alan Milburn, gave a speech in
mid September 2006, arguing that tax reform should remain open for debate,
which was interpreted by the Guardian as a thinly veiled show of support for
Stephen Byers, whose proposals to abolish inheritance tax apparently had
573
36 id., at para. 27.
37 Cretney, op. cit., n. 34, at p. 285.
38 id. In this, Cretney eschews the Benthamite position. M. West, `The Theory of the
Inheritance Tax' (1893) 8 Political Science Q. 426±44, at 427.
39 Lord Walker explained that calling CTT's successor an inheritance tax is incorrect,
for, `[i]n truth inheritance tax is a misnomer for a donor-based mutation tax, a hybrid
between a gifts tax and estate duty, with a structure that is already looking both
rambling and ramshackle.' R. Walker, `Reflections on the Finance Act 1894 (1994)
Brit. Tax Rev. 368, at 373.
40 G. Serjeant, `Reports of this Tax's Death Are Greatly Exaggerated' Times,24
August 2006, 55.
41 id.
42 id.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
been `stamped on' by the Treasury.
43
The Times explained that the
Treasury's position was entirely predictable, since the inheritance tax had
been expected to raise £3.6 billion in 2006, and it was thus unlikely that the
Treasury would be keen to forego such an important source of revenue.
44
Abolishing the inheritance tax also was thought to be contrary to what the
Times described as Gordon Brown's personal belief in `starting equal if not
equal outcomes'.
45
The tabloid Daily Express has conducted a sustained campaign for the
repeal of inheritance taxation.
46
Typical of its efforts is an article entitled,
`Cheers for Death Tax Vow', reporting that David Cameron `was under
enormous pressure . . . after Tory activists overwhelmingly backed the
crusade to scrap inheritance tax.'
47
The Daily Express's campaign received a
great deal of ammunition from reaction to Gordon Brown's 2006 Budget.
48
On 22 March 2006, Brown announced significant changes to the treatment of
trusts and the reach of inheritance tax law,
49
which were widely criticized.
50
Shadow Chancellor George Osborne was quoted in the press as saying that
the proposals were:
hugely damaging to millions of people. It is only ideological spite that is
stopping them backing down. That is what happens when you get a socialist as
chancellor.
51
The changes were decried as `retrospective' legislation in the British Tax
Review (although the author noted that this form of rule making is not
unheard of in fiscal law).
52
The government largely has stood firm since
574
43 P. Wintour, `Milburn sets out radical post-Blair manifesto: Ex-minister insists party
must have wide debate: School, tax and Commons reforms among proposals'
Guardian,15September 2006, 11.
44 Serjeant, op. cit., n. 40.
45 id.
46 A. Little, `Our Death Tax Campaign is No. 1 at No. 10' Daily Express,21February
2007). An anonymous referee for this journal cautions that this campaign should be
kept in perspective, and questions whether it is surprising that the Express has not
found more mainstream support for the perennially popular idea of doing away with
a form of taxation.
47 M. Hall, `Cheers for Death Tax Vow' Daily Express,4October 2006.
48 See discussion of this effect in `House Price Growth and HM Treasury', TaxPayers'
Alliance at e.com/news/theme_blog.php?theme=
Inheritance+Tax>.
49 See Budget at easury.gov.uk/budget/budget_06/
bud_bud06_index.cfm>.
50 See M. Warburton, `Inheritance tax now affects us all' Sunday Telegraph,22
October 2006, 4; R. Budden, `Treasury signals ``all change'' on annuity rule'
Financial Times,21October 2006, 1.
51 J. Lappin, `Revenue Said Brown's IHT Shock Was Crazy' MoneyMarketing,18
May 2006, 41.
52 See A. Harper, `Tax Post Facto' (2006) 4 Brit. Tax Rev. 395.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
then, although Gordon Brown (then as Chancellor) later insisted that the new
legislation would be targeted at `avoiders' only.
53
The Budget protest was led by activists who could be described as
interested parties, and it is important perhaps to keep the Express campaign
within a certain, populist, context. Nonetheless it is clear that the subject
with which theories of economic inheritance will need to deal currently is
fraught with a peculiar form of emotional, political debate. The protest over
the 2006 Budget, in particular, serves to emphasize that the emotional impact
of inheritance taxation often has not been appreciated by politicians.
Churchill, for example, did not appreciate it, and famously believed that the
`psychological' impact of death duties was less `onerous' than that of income
taxation.
54
Indeed, Daunton reveals that Churchill held as a `political
principle' the value of increasing death duties so as to fund reductions in
income tax.
55
Underappreciation of the impact of inheritance, culturally, plays an
important role in the story of the repeal of the United States estate tax.
Graetz and Shapiro explain that proponents of inheritance tax have a
tendency to rest on its easy logic, or `science', too comfortably, whilst
missing the fact that (in recent years) movements to repeal an `immoral'
(that is, double taxing and, ironically, non-progressive) tax were moving
from fringe to mainstream discourse.
56
In the United States, it is particularly striking how the early twentieth-
century concern about `robber barons'
57
has shifted, especially given that the
Economic Growth and Tax Reconciliation Act of 2001, which was signed by
George W. Bush on 7 June 2001,
58
was supported by a strong majority of
taxpayers who likely never would own estates that would cross the threshold
for inheritance taxation.
59
Graetz and Shapiro, however, warn against
treating the `what were US taxpayers thinking?' question too delicately,
reminding us that `Stories Trump Science'.
60
It also would be a mistake to
characterize the repeal of the United States inheritance tax as a heated battle
575
53
G. Milland, `Climbdown on death tax' Daily Express,9May 2006, 8. For the new rules
on trusts, see Finance Act 2006, s. 156, detailing the amendments to both the
Inheritance Tax Act 1984 and the Taxation of Chargeable Gains Act 1992. Finance Act
2006 s. 156 and Sched. 20 eventually contained significant revisions to the treatment of
interest in possession trusts, accumulation and maintenance trusts, lifetime gifts, dis-
abled trusts and discretionary trusts. For the treatment of `settled' property, see IHTA
1984, Pt. III, ss. 43±93, as amended in 1986 and by the Finance Act 2006, Sched. 20.
54
M. Daunton, Just Taxes: The Politics of Taxation in Britain 1914±1979 (2002) at 132.
55 id.
56 id., at p. 226.
57
J.D. Trout and S.A. Buttar, `Resurrecting ``Death Taxes'':Inheritance, Redistribution,
and the Science of Happiness' (2002) 16 J. of Law & Politics 765±847, at 777.
58 Economic Growth and Tax Relief Reconciliation Act of 2001, Pub. L.No. 107±16,
115 Stat. 38 (codified in 26 U.S.C.).
59 See Graetz and Shapiro, op. cit., n. 9, `A Political Mystery', pp. 3±11.
60 id., ch. 20.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
± Graetz and Shapiro stress that `[i]n fact, it was the low intensity of public
opinion about tax questions in general, and the estate tax in particular, that
made the tax vulnerable to repeal.'
61
The blame for this apathy can be placed
at the door of fiscal legislation itself, which was little understood.
62
Blame also may be attributed to what would appear to be a basic fear in
some taxpayers about inheritance tax. For example, over thirty years ago,
Tullock described how the proponents of inheritance taxation may not have
considered thoroughly the endgame of their platform:
The man with a wife and two children and a large mortgage on his house could
not only not have an insurance policy which would pay off the mortgage in the
event of his death, he could not even leave the house to his wife if it were in
his possession free and clear.
63
Inheritance taxation is a step before the situation described, but the fear of it
does seem to touch upon a difficult to describe cogently, but nonetheless
basic apprehension in some taxpayers.
STARTING THE DISCUSSION: UPDATING EARLY TWENTIETH
CENTURY, US-CENTRIC DISCOURSE WITH THEORIES OF
ECONOMIC INHERITANCE
How is inheritance tax law in the United Kingdom presently discussed?
Although the answer may be surprising, the language and issues largely are
framed by the debates which occurred at the beginning of 1900s, in the
United States, during a push to introduce a federal estate tax.
64
Writers of
that era focused on the contributions of J.S. Mill, in particular, to economic
inheritance, especially his argument that progressive taxation could be
justified for inheritances (if not for taxation more generally).
65
Although
there is some confusion as to Mill's exact views on redistribution, Winch
writes that (according to Mill's `disciple Bain'
66
) Mill hoped that inheritance
taxation would `pull down all large fortunes in two generations'.
67
576
61 id., p. 254.
62 Braithwaite observes that `[o]ne result of a protracted dynamic of rules multiplying
exponentially is that no one can keep them in their mind.' J. Braithwaite, Markets in
Vice, Markets in Virtue (2005) at 148.
63 G. Tullock, `Inheritance Rejustified' (1973) 16 J. Law & Economics 425±8, at 425.
64 A.K. Pactor, `The moral case for the estate tax' (2003) 2003 New Directions for
Philanthropic Fundraising 25. See, also, W.G. Gale and J.K. Scholz, `Inter-
generational Transfers and the Accumulation of Wealth' (1994) 8 J. of Economic
Perspectives 145, at 146.
65 J.S. Mill, Principles of Political Economy (1909/1848) Bk. V, ch. II, v. 2.14±2.15.
66 A Scottish philosopher who was a `personal friend' of Mill's, see A. Bain, John
Stuart Mill: A Criticism with Personal Recollections (2004/1882).
67 D. Winch, `Review Essay: Mills as Romantic Idealist' (2004) 26 J. of the History of
Economic Thought 543±55, at 551, citing Bain, id., at p. 89. In 2004, however,
Capaldi wrote that `Mill was sceptical about schemes for redistribution'; Winch, id.,
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
Leading inheritance tax writers of the early twentieth century included
both Max West and the noted American economist and tax legal theorist,
E.R.A. Seligman, who placed an interesting slant on the class aspiration
debate when he wrote that Mill `maintained that the only test of just taxation
was equality of sacrifice'.
68
In other words, a formula must be found whereby
the rich man's sacrifice to taxation is equal to the poor man's. Seligman
described this as a very French idea: `the standpoint of Montesquieu,
Montyon, and Say among the French writers, and of Craig, Buchanan and
Sayer among the English writers.'
69
The sacrifices of class sustainability or
upward mobility may or may not be equivalent to the hardships ensured by
the `poor man', but, the argument suggests, their loss is felt.
70
Conversely, Max West suggested that there are two ways of looking at
inheritance taxes: `. .. as a fiscal imposition, but also as a modification of the
law of inheritance and bequest.'
71
From a legal perspective, the inheritance tax
may be explained as a limitation on a right (to dispose of property on death),
and perhaps by the objective to distribute wealth more equitably.
72
As a `fiscal
imposition', West suggests, the inheritance tax is either a tax or a fee: `as a
payment in return for benefits received, or as a public contribution according
to the ability of the taxpayer.'
73
The `benefits received' might include either
government services enjoyed over a lifetime,
74
generally; services specific to
the estate; services related to the expenses of probate courts; or, finally,
payment for a presumed amount of tax avoided over a lifetime.
75
The `benefits received' argument is interesting, but Seligman pointed out
some potential difficulties with this:
The rich man sends his children to private schools and colleges; the poor man
has his family educated in the public schools. The rich man has his street
swept by his own hired laborer; the poor man has his cleaned at the expense of
the city . . . Logically, thus, it might seem that the poor man should then pay
proportionally more than the rich man.
76
577
quoting N. Capaldi, John Stuart Mill: A Biography (2004), at p. 299. Winch (at fn.
26, citing Capaldi, at p. 204 and n. 390) addresses the confusion, and argues that the
evidence appears to favour Mills as a redistributionist. He notes, however, that
`Capaldi softens this by maintaining that the inheritance tax was not an estate tax
because it could be avoided through intra-family redistribution'. In other words, Mill
may have been less sceptical about the inheritance tax, but in any case the focus of
his attention was a different form of estate taxation.
68 E.R.A. Seligman, `The Theory of Progressive Taxation' (1893) 8 Political Science
Q. 220, at 234.
69 id.
70 See, generally, J.E. Roemer, `Why the poor do not expropriate the rich: an old
argument in new garb' (1998) 70 J. of Public Economics 399.
71 West, op. cit., n. 38, at p. 426.
72 id.
73 id.
74 id.
75 id.
76 Seligman, op. cit., n. 68, at p. 229.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
In the United Kingdom during this era, the exact opposite of Seligman's
(tongue-in-cheek) proposal w as considered. Rignano's lat e-eighteenth-
century suggestion that the amount of tax levied on an estate should
increase proportionately to the age of the estate (such that an estate
bequeathed from a parent to a child will be taxed less heavily than one
passed from a grandparent to a child) received a great deal of attention in
Parliament in the late 1920s.
77
Although Mann described this as a `naõÈve
plan' that `received more a ttention than it deserved',
78
the Colwyn
Committee `found the principle in itself attractive' and suggested `that it
may in course of time have useful developments'.
79
The anti-inheritance tax movement in the United Kingdom has focused
on, among other things, the extent to which inheritance tax avoidance
benefits the wealthy, and arguments that inheritance taxation is fair and
`targeted'.
80
Duff, warning that inheritance taxation is `under pressure' in the
United Kingdom, has analysed the `political challenges' which may make its
retention difficult, despite its benefits.
81
Massone et al. are similarly
disheartened by the political threats to inheritance taxation, and suggest that
earmarking funds collected for the benefit of `the poor' might be a way of
salvaging them.
82
Conversely, Bracewell-Milnes has argued that inheritance
taxation causes a great deal of harm to the economy in the United Kingdom,
and has long argued for its abolition.
83
These are standard arguments of US-centric, early-twentieth century
discourse. This paper proposes that the discussion should be updated, by
integrating sociological theories of economic inheritance. This is not to
suggest, however, that inheritance taxation, specifically, is a common topic
within economic inheritance analyses ± far from it. Indeed, inheritance tax is
not a frequent target of sociologists.
84
Described by MacNamee and Miller
578
77 F.K. Mann, `The Sociology of Taxation' (1943) 5 Rev. of Politics 225, at 235,
discussing E. Rignano, Di un socialismo in accordo colla dottrina economica
liberale (1901).
78 Mann, id.
79 id., citing Report of the Committee on National Debt and Taxation (1927; Cmnd.
2800) 316.
80 Pratten, op. cit., n. 13, pp. 74±5. The author concludes that inheritance tax is neither
fair nor targeted, and that Gordon Brown's `numbers are misleading'.
81 Duff, op. cit., n. 7, p. 46.
82 Massone et al., op. cit., n. 3, p. 1.
83
See B. Bracewell-Milnes, `Euthanasia for Death Duties: Putting Inheritance Tax Out of
its Misery' (2002) Institute for Economic Affairs Monograph, and the review by J.
Tiley, `Publication Review, Euthanasia for Death Duties: Putting Inheritance Tax Out
Of Its Misery, Barry Bracewell-Milnes' (2003) 3 Brit. Tax Rev. 255; also, B.
Bracewell-Milnes, `The Hidden Costs of Inheritance Taxation' in Is Inheritance
Legitimate?, eds. G. Erreygers and T. Vandevelde (1997) 156±201; B. Bracewell-
Milnes, The Wealth of Giving: Every One in His Inheritance (1989); and B. Bracewell-
Milnes, `Unquoted Companies and Inheritance Tax' (1995) 23 Intertax 614.
84 See R.B. Avery and M.S. Rendall, `Lifetime Inheritances of Three Generations of
Whites and Blacks' (2002) 107 Am. J. of Sociology 1300, at 1301; P. Mullins, `The
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
as a `sociological lacuna', inheritance tax is `a frequently mentioned but
rarely examined feature of stratification systems'.
85
By `stratification',
MacNamee and Miller explain, they mean that sociology has preferred to
examine, for example, a family's income as opposed to its `wealth', and
`individual attainment' as opposed to inherited wealth.
86
They suggest that
reasons for this reluctance may stem from the fact that inherited advantage is
an uncomfortable subject.
87
Additionally, the inheritance of estates is a very
difficult subject to study, given the layers of subterfuge that the wealthy will
employ to avoid taxation.
88
This section will provide a brief analysis of the arguments with which a
revived sociological analysis of inheritance taxation might engage. Its aim is
to provide a foundation for consideration of the current status of inheritance
tax law. It will also reveal that there is much potential for a revived discourse.
Closer inspection of this `lacuna' reveals, for example, Giddens, one of
the few sociologists who has addressed inheritance tax directly.
89
Writing
from the centre-left,
90
Giddens describes inheritance taxation as the `obvious
579
Line of Descent in the Intergenerational Transmission of Domestic Property' (2000)
15 Housing Studies 683, at 685
85 S.J. McNamee and R.K. Miller Jr., `Estate Inheritance: A Sociological Lacuna'
(1989) 59 Sociological Inquiry 7±29, at 1.
86 id.
87 id.
88 id., at p. 2. Additionally, tax avoidance, generally, typically is described as a diffi-
cult subject for sociological study. See R. Mason and L.D. Calvin, `A Study of
Admitted Income Tax Evasion' (1978) 13 Law & Society Rev. 73, at 75±7; J.
Hasseldine and Z. Li, `More tax evasion research required in new millennium'
(1999) 31 Crime, Law and Social Change 91; M Bergman, `Who Pays for Social
Policy? A Study on Taxes and Trust' (2002) 31 J. of Social Policy 289, at 289; D.J.
McBarnet and C. Whelan, Creative Accounting and the Cross-eyed Javelin Thrower
(1999) at 240; and A. Mumford, Taxing Culture: Towards a Theory of Tax
Collection Law (2001) at 38±40, discussing `rough justice' and the differences in
attitudes towards tax avoidance in the United States and the United Kingdom.
89 This is a development apart from standard Third Way discourse. J. Lewis and R.
Surender, Welfare State Change: Towards a Third Way? (2004) at 42: `While there
are occasional references to inheritance tax in Third Way literature, and occasional
screeds directed at ``fat cat'' corporate executives, the Third Way simply does not
interrogate the morality of property incomes in the systematic way that the
functionalists did.'
90 See A. Giddens, The Progressive Manifesto: New Ideas for the Centre-left (2003).
On the question of centre-left discourse, see S. White, `Review Article: Social
Rights and Social Contract ± Political Theory and the New Welfare Politics' (2000)
30 Brit. J. of Political Science 507, at 520, noting that: `In contemporary centre-left
policy discussion, . . . there seems relatively little interest in the revival of
inheritance or wealth transfer taxation, and what discussion there is of this issue
tends to be divorced from the debate surrounding welfare reform.' White stresses
that this statement does not apply equally to the United States and the United
Kingdom, and (at fn. 35) notes that early Blair Cabinet advisors such as Peter
Mandelson and Roger Liddle proposed reforming inheritance tax so as to benefit
newly married couples.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
mechanism for egalitarian policies.'
91
He argues against its abolition, and
suggests that it should be more progressive, and should allow fewer
exemptions.
92
Giddens recommends that more people should pay inheritance
tax in the United Kingdom than do currently, and approves of suggestions
that `the extra money generated could be spent on a trust fund for children, or
for long-term care for the frail elderly.'
93
This indicates both a confidence in
the stability of inheritance tax (it is here to stay; indeed, let us increase its
reach), and an effort to engage public discourse on the value of inheritance
taxation.
94
Is this confidence well placed? Durkheim would suggest that the issue
perhaps is a bit more complicated. Perhaps best known to socio-legal
scholars for his contribution of the concept of organic solidarity,
95
or for
his work with restitutive law,
96
Durkheim may not be one of the first
people considered in a debate about inheritance tax law, but he should be.
As he implicitly acknowledges,
97
Giddens draws from a tradition within
which Durkheim is perhaps one of the most famous critics of inherited
wealth. Indeed, Durkheim `bitterly' criticized inheritance, describing it as
inappropriate in a society which aspired to be egalitarian and just.
98
Because the wealth that results from inheritance is neither earned nor
deserved, he argued, the entire social contract is `invalidate[d]'.
99
Durk-
heim did recognize a `right' of inheritance, or a right to leave a will, as an
essential aspect of the development of what he described as `the conjugal
580
91 A. Giddens, Europe in the Global Age (2006) at 83.
92 id., at pp. 83±4.
93
id., at p. 84. Hypothecation does not appear to be a favoured method of the Prime
Minister, given his experience with environmental taxation. For a complete analysis of
this, see the impressive Stern Review, at
reviews/stern_review_economics_climate_change/sternreview_ index.cfm>.
94 Although by recommending something akin to the earmarking of inheritance
taxation, it reflects, perhaps, a nervousness about the propriety of inheritance
taxation, dissimilar to the confident quote which opened this article.
95
Durkheim postulates that `the bond of solidarity has changed during the course of
social evolution, and he seeks to identify the causes and consequences of this change.'
W. Pope and B.D. Johnson, `Inside Organic Solidarity' (1983) 48 Am. Sociological
Rev. 681, at 681, citing E. Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society (1997).
96 Cotterrell explains that `[r]estitutive law .. . reflects relations of a totally different
character from those which penal law reflects.' R.B.M. Cotterrell, `Durkheim on
Legal Development and Social Solidarity' (1977) 4 Brit. J. of Law and Society 241,
at 242, citing Durkheim, id. Whereas penal law changes the life of the offender,
restitutive law attempts to restore things to the way they `were'. It is `not simply
mediation of private interests' (Cotterrell, at p. 247) but `a social thing and has a
totally different object than the interests of the pleaders'.
97 `Giddens suggests that ``. .. moral individualism is one area in which the conscience
collective . . . becomes strengthened as organic solidarity expands''.' C.R. Chandler,
`Durkheim and Individualism: A Comment on Messner' (1984) 63 Social Forces
571, at 571.
98 E. Durkheim and M.O. Hill, Professional Ethics and Civic Morals (1992) at xxv.
99 id., at p. 213.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
family',
100
however, but this was part of an account which considered the
family as an economic institution which would diminish in importance.
101
Indeed, he suggested that as society evolved away from the family, people
would leave their property to business and other economic organizations.
102
Strikingly, although Marx may be thought to be a more obvious candidate
than Durkheim in an analysis of economic inheritance, it is nonetheless the
case that, although valuable, he offers less. Indeed, what Marx offers to tax
lawyers, generally, is limited, simply because he did not frequently address
tax.
103
Marx also did not address inheritance specifically, but included it
within his consideration of the `relations of production'.
104
Nonetheless, the
study of inheritance still does not fit easily within Marxian analysis because,
as Beckert, observed:
[w]hile it is one thing to acknowledge the importance of non-market based
transfers in modern capitalist societies it is quite another to understand the
principles of their regulation and their implications.
105
Beckert reminds us, however, that bequeathing property is an economic
act, capable of being distinguished from other economic acts typical of a
market economy in that it is not based on contract.
106
Rather, it is based on
`ascription', and as a result inheritance is `problematic', `thickly embedded'
± and, as a result, not easily studied.
107
The problematization of inheritance
581
100 E. Durkheim, `The Conjugal Family' in Emile Durkheim on Institutional Analysis,
ed. and tr. by M. Traugott (1978) 229, at 232. See, also, G. Simpson, `A Durkheim
Fragment' (1965) 70 Am. J. of Sociology 527.
101 T.P. Schwartz, `Durkheim's Prediction about the Declining importance of the
Family and Inheritance: Evidence From the Wills of Providence, 1775±1985' (1996)
37 Sociological Q. 503.
102 id.
103 See, generally, J. Friedman, `Marxism, Structuralism and Vulgar Materialism'
(1974) 9 Man 444.
104 R. Swedberg, `The case for an economic sociology of law' (2003) 32 Theory and
Society 1, at 6. Swedberg engages with (an earlier edition of) K. Marx and V.I.
Lenin, Capital: The Communist Manifesto and Other Writings (1932). For more on
the Marxian concept of the `relations of production', see H. Lefebvre, The Survival
of Capitalism: Reproduction of the Relations of Production (1978); R.C. Edwards,
`The social relations of production at the point of production' in Complex Organiza-
tions: Critical Perspectives, eds. M. Zey-Ferrell and M. Aiken (1981) 156; R.C.
Edwards, `The Social Relations of Production in The Firm and Labor Market
Structure' (1975) 5 Politics & Society 83. Essentially, this is discussed in terms of
the relationships that build between humans in the creation and distribution of
material wealth. The idea is described by Foucault as integral to the `question of
power': `while the human subject is placed in relations of production and of
signification, he is equally placed in power relations which are very complex.' M.
Foucault, `The Subject and Power' (1982) 8 Critical Inquiry 777.
105 J. Beckert, `Political and Social Interests in the Transfer of Property' (2006) 46
European J. of Sociology 359, at 359.
106 id., at p. 367.
107 id. The reason for this is that inheritance `cannot be functionally differentiated from
normative concerns the way that market transfers can.'
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
results in part from the legal system which supports it, and the extent to
which the `privileged group', as E.P. Thompson described them, have
manipulated laws to secure their own families' wealth.
108
Examples of this
are provided by Beckert, whose 2004 book on the sociology of inheritance
compares what might broadly be described as patterns of justification for
inheritance (in the post-Durkheim era) in three countries: the United States,
Germany, and France.
109
Although his approach has been described as
Weberian, the objective of his book is to confirm the importance of
Durkheim to this area of study.
110
For example, Durkheim (by contrast with
Marx) was concerned with the emotional and social attachment that societies
have fostered for property over the centuries.
111
This concern was rooted in a
desire to eliminate any inequitable advantage, however, including inherited
property.
112
Beckert reminds us that analyses of inheritance tax law demand con-
sideration of Durkheim. Interestingly, Cotterrell notes that Durkheim's
analysis of the relationship between people and property is likely to be `odd'
to lawyers, who view property as `a variable set of legal relationships
between persons with respect to things'.
113
This insight may have particular
importance for the analysis of inheritance tax, which often stumbles against
the emotive significance of the family home. The motives behind bequests
are considered `crucial' by the economists and sociologists who study
inheritance.
114
The reason for this is that identification of motives will
enable economists, in particular, to discern how different incentives will
582
108 J. Goody, J. Thirsk, and E. Thompson (eds.), Family and Inheritance: Rural Society
in Western Europe 1200±1800 (1978) at 358±60.
109 Further analyses undoubtedly will be provided by the release of the Mirrlees Report.
Publications on the progress of the review may be found at
mirrleesreview/publications.php>. See, also, I. Young, `Towards a better tax
system' (2007) 2 Taxline 3.
110 R. Swedberg, `Book Review of Beckert's Unverdienstes VermoÈgen' (2005) 6
Economic Sociology: European Electronic Newsletter at 44.
111 Swedberg, op. cit., n. 104. See, also, R.B.M. Cotterrell, Emile Durkheim: Law in a
Moral Domain (1999) at 134: `Durkheim treats property as a relationship between a
person and a thing.'
112 W.J. Ramp, `Durkheim and the Unthought: Some Dilemmas of Modernity' (2001)
26 Cnd. J. of Sociology 89, at 100; T. Noble, `Correspondence' (1980) 31 Brit. J. of
Sociology 580, at 581; M.A. Lamanna, Emile Durkheim on the Family (2001) at 57,
60. Durkheim did not believe that this would eliminate all unfair advantage,
although he is sometimes criticized for suggesting that it would. See J.C. Alexander,
The Cambridge Companion to Durkheim (2005) at 352±3.
113 Cotterrell, op. cit., n. 111, at p. 134.
114 M. Kohli, `Intergenerational transfers and inheritance: A comparative view' (2004)
Springer Annual Review of Gerontology and Geriatrics: Intergenerational relations
across time and place at 268. This is also suggested throughout H. Cremer and P.
Pestieau, `Wealth transfer taxation: a survey of the theoretical literature' in
Handbook on the Economics of Giving, Reciprocity and Altruism, eds. L.-A. GeÂrard-
Varet, S.-C. Kolm, and J. Mercier Ythier (2006).
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
impact upon the decision as to legacies.
115
Although controlling `family'
decisions might appear to be intrusive, these are issues that should not be left
to the private sphere, for, as Warren argued, `[i]nheritance has enormous
effects upon social inequality'.
116
This situation is complicated by the fact that these decisions still are
made, typically, within the context of relationships that are the subject of
enormous state persuasion as to behaviour ± for example, parents are
encouraged to take care of their children (when they are young, at least) and
this sort of behaviour is difficult to abandon.
117
A typical example of this
sort of argument is presented by Brown (in 1961):
[i]t is, in short, illogical to abolish completely the inheritance of wealth unless
we also abolish the family and make all children wards of the state.
118
A potentially valuable contribution to a modern analysis of inheritance tax
law would include acknowledgment that the value of the modern family
home, or, more clearly, the value of providing financially for one's children,
transcends the purely economic. Parenthood is defined by its sacrifices, both
financial and emotional. Modern society expects parents to provide con-
tinuous care for their children, even to their own detriment.
119
This is in
contrast to generations ago, when children were `a pretty good economic
bargain'.
120
The value of the labour provided by children more than
compensated for the costs of clothing and food.
121
This was during a time
when families might be `cash poor', and the only real item of value which
they possessed was land.
122
Children today, however, are popularly perceived as more of an emotional
investment, than an economic decision.
123
Indeed, they make little economic
sense, and few taxpayers would have them solely for profit.
124
Real property,
however, continues to be a source of wealth. To begin to understand the
emotional reactions to inheritance tax, however, the relationship between
economics and parenting requires consideration.
583
115 Kohli, id.
116 T. Warren, `Moving beyond the gender wealth gap: On gender, class, ethnicity, and
wealth inequalities in the United Kingdom' (2006) 12 Feminist Economics 195, at
199.
117 This is discussed throughout D.N. Lye, `Adult Child-Parent Relationships' (1996)
22 Annual Rev. of Sociology 79.
118 H.G. Brown, `Criteria for a Rational Tax System' (1961) 20 Am. J. of Economics
and Sociology 443, at 445±6.
119 A.L. Alstott, No Exit: What Parents Owe Their Children and What Society Owes
Parents (2004) 50.
120 id.
121 id.
122 id.
123 id. See K.M. Nomaguchi and M.A. Milkie, `Costs and Rewards of Children: The
Effects of Becoming a Parent on Adults' Lives' (2003) 65 J. of Marriage and
Family 356.
124 Alstott, op. cit., n. 119, p. 51.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
The problem is defined by Alstott, who suggests that `. . . the No exit
obligation . . . is the defining feature of modern parenthood.'
125
She defines
the `No Exit' obligation as:
...not merely the obligation not to abandon one's children by the roadside, but
also the much harder, more intensive, and crucially important duty to create
the intimacy, stability, and loyalty that Goldstein, Freud and Solnit
describe.
126
The duty to provide `continuity of care' to children is an onerous, expensive
and controversial obligation.
127
Amongst its various requirements is that
parents recognize that high-quality care provided consistently by the same
carer(s) is more valuable than otherwise effective care provided by a variety
of people.
128
This is an expensive obligation on the modern parent, and
Alstott explores potential `compensation' that society might owe to parents
in order to enable them to achieve it.
129
It is difficult to discontinue such a duty of care. Inheritance tax, thus,
might represent an interference with the `No Exit Obligation'. Death is the
moment when the modern, `No Exit Obligation' parent must confront old-
fashioned concerns about `privileges which enrich them at the expense of
their poorer fellows'.
130
Given the terminal way in which this obligation has
been fashioned, its abandonment is hardly likely to be intuitive.
Duff has argued that:
...the initial enactment of wealth transfer taxes at the turn of the [last] century
and developments in family law . . . signal the displacement of the feudal and
patriarchal family by a conception of the family that is neither dynastic nor
organic, but egalitarian and pluralistic.
131
These developments in tax law, however, did not keep pace with the
development of the `No Exit Obligation'. Rather, engagement with Mill's
views of inherited wealth developed into discussions of Rawls, and liberal
views of inheritance taxation.
132
Analyses progressed,
133
but did not accord
the changing emotional and economic contexts of parenthood sufficient
attention. The stage was set for conflict.
584
125 id.
126 id., p. 52.
127 id., p. 30.
128 id. This idea also is discussed throughout Alstott's book.
129 id.
130 Harcourt, n. 31 above.
131 D.G. Duff, `Taxing Inherited Wealth: A Philosophical Argument' (1993) VI Cnd. J.
of Law and Jurisprudence 3±62, at 61.
132 See J. Rawls, `Justice as Fairness' (1958) 67 Philosophical Rev. 164, and J.S. Mill,
Principles of Political Economy: With Some of Their Applications to Social
Philosophy (1891). See discussion in E.J. McCaffery, `The Political Liberal Case
Against the Estate Tax' (1994) 23 Philosophy and Public Affairs 281±312.
133 Pactor, op. cit., n. 64.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
REVIVING THE DISCOURSE OF INHERITANCE TAX LAW
The consideration of the position of `adult' children, at least, might assist
analyses of inheritance taxation in moving beyond the purely political, and
questions of liberal, socio-economic justice. Their consideration in legal
context, however, and queries as to the `rights' adult children may or may
not have, must acknowledge the extent to which imagery of rights has been
used for political capital.
134
When discussing inheritance taxation, questions
of terminology are politically charged.
Acknowledgment of the links formed within the `conjugal family' through
economic work,
135
however, could cast light upon previously ignored
subtleties of this discourse.
136
It also may allow serious discussion of the
(perhaps, less attractive) alternatives to inheritance taxation. For example, as
Buttenheim argued, the progressive element of inheritance taxation may
render it a palatable alternative to real estate taxation, which is less progres-
sive.
137
This, potentially, is an important point for a renewed inheritance tax
debate.
Perhaps a reason why this point is seldom raised lies in the criticism that
inheritance tax is inefficient, and discourages saving.
138
Whilst there is
consensus
139
across the political divide that these negative impacts, or
`leaks',
140
exist, there is disagreement as to how great a problem this is.
Predictably, those on the right insist that this problem is very grave, whereas
those on the left suggest that any economic efficiency that is lost is worth the
sacrifice.
141
A (somewhat basic) explanation of this criticism is that workers
will have less incentive to produce, and less incentive to save, if such capital
585
134 The `culture of rights' literature is very useful in this context. See, for example, S.
Bhatia, `Can We Return to the Concept of Duty in a Culture of Rights? Implications
for Morality and Identity' (2000) 6 Culture & Psychology 303; J.K. Cowan, M.B.
Dembour, and R. Wilson, Culture and Rights (2001).
135 Durkheim, op. cit., n. 100, at s. 232.
136 See, also, Tiley, op. cit., n. 14, at p. 319: `The author is convinced that there is much
sense in the principle behind these older duties that consanguinity mattered and was
a legitimate call on generosity.'
137 H.S. Buttenheim, `The Relation of Housing to Taxation' (1933±1934) 1 Law &
Contemporary Problems 198±295, at 205.
138 A. Auerbach, IFS Press Release: `Inheritance tax still has a role to play, says Alan
Auerbach in IFS Annual Lecture' at .
139 But compare Murphy and Nagel, op. cit., n. 26, at p. 143.
140 Graetz and Shapiro, op. cit., n. 9, p. 228.
141 id., pp. 228±9. For example, in 1960s United States political discourse, politicians
on the left supported what Zelizer has described as `anti-growthmanship': J.E.
Zelizer, Taxing America ± Wilbur D. Mills, Congress, and the State, 1945±1975
(1998) 171. The suggestion was that `[p]olicies that focused on growth failed to
address the main needs of society.' As an alternative, `[p]ublic policy should thus
focus on structural inequalities that persisted over time.'
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
will be subject to tax.
142
Economies benefit from workers trying to create as
much as possible,
143
thus, economies as a whole work less efficiently when
taxes on capital, like inheritance taxes, are present.
144
Seligman would have responded to challenges that taxation can have a
negative effect on `industry and saving' by cautioning that `. .. it is a mistake
to assume that larger fortunes are always the result of individual saving.'
145
Indeed, the bottom line of many of these criticisms, Seligman suggested, was
`an argument . . . against taxation in general'.
146
Indeed, Adams argued that
all saving is not necessarily, a priori, a good thing, and that there might come
a point when saving, in effect, becomes hoarding.
147
Though he conceded
that the criticism that inheritance taxation impairs the incentive to save was
the `most formidable charge against it', he maintained that the more one
saved, the greater the probability that an estate would be `wasted' by
beneficiaries.
148
The debate may be revived by focusing on the fact that inheritance taxes
are a quintessentially progressive tax.
149
Societal reaction to progressivity is
a favoured topic of sociological analysis, which has revealed the assumptions
behind the political rhetoric.
150
The temporary abolition of inheritance tax in
the United States has been presented as a blow for progressivity, and a `high-
profile' victory for regressivity.
151
The wide popular support that this aboli-
tion received is in this context puzzling, considering that, if the wealthier
sections of society that normally would pay inheritance tax have been
586
142 See A. Dixit and J. Londregan, `Redistributive Politics and Economic Efficiency'
(1995) 89 Am. Political Science Rev. 856, which analyses the differences between
politically efficient, and economically efficient, distribution.
143 Even though (in socialist economies, as well) the rewards are often distributed
unequally. For a discussion of this, in the context of theories of stratification, see,
generally, A.G.Walder,`Property Rights and Stratification in Socialist
Redistributive Economies' (1992) 57 Am. Sociological Rev. 524.
144 This is analysed throughout M.J. Boskin, `Taxation, Saving, and the Rate of Interest'
(1978) 86 J. of Political Economy 3.
145 Seligman, op. cit., n. 68, at p. 248. Although it is important not to assume a United
States/United Kingdom parallel, Seligman was a scholar of United Kingdom tax
law, and frequently combined analyses of the two tax systems.
146 id.
147 T.S. Adams, `Effect of Income and Inheritance Taxes on the Distribution of Wealth'
(1915) 5 Am. Economic Rev. 234±44, at 238.
148 id., at p. 240.
149 G. Brennan and J.M. Buchanan, The Power To Tax: Analytical Foundations of a
Fiscal Constitution (1980) at 36.
150 See J. Edlund, `Attitudes towards Tax Reform and Progressive Taxation: Sweden
1991±96' (1999) 42 Acta Sociologica 337; Mann, op. cit., n. 77, at pp. 231±4, and
M.P. Allen and J.L. Campbell, `State Revenue Extraction from Different Income
Groups: Variations in Tax Progressivity in the United States, 1916 to 1986' (1994)
59 Am. Sociological Rev. 169.
151 L.A. Fennell, `Hyperopia in Public Finance' in Behavioral Public Finance, eds. E.J.
McCaffery and J. Slemrod (2006) 141±72, at 161±2.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
relieved of this burden, then, by definition, less wealthy taxpayers are going
to need to contribute more, just to maintain the status quo.
152
This may be
due to the fact that, as Harper suggests, `[e]state and gift tax legislation is
largely used as an instrument of policy to influence behaviour, typically
wealth distribution, retention or investment patterns.'
153
Whether they are
effective inducements for behaviour, however, is not clear. Research has
suggested that wealthy people do not always find the avoidance of
inheritance taxes to be a good incentive to give away their wealth during
their lifetimes.
154
James writes that `[p]ossibly therefore such taxes might be
considered to be voluntary taxes paid by those who dislike their relatives
even more than they dislike paying tax.'
155
Anti-inheritance tax rhetoric has benefited from research suggesting that it
is not clear that an inheritance tax in fact does have a positive effect on the
redistribution of wealth.
156
Estate taxes may produce a sort of domino
effect.
157
First, many taxpayers may choose to save less.
158
Secondly, a lower
`capital labor ratio' may result, in that, essentially, the economy suffers from
a lack of capital, so that there is an increase in the `share of capital' ± or,
simply, capital increases in value.
159
Generally, as Stiglitz warned, income
from capital is `more unequally distributed', which ultimately may lead to the
rich becoming richer.
160
If this is the case, then arguments about the fairness
of inheritance taxation are important, because they enable consideration of
what, beyond redistribution, such taxation may achieve.
FAIRNESS AND `THE FAMILY HOME'
The point Stiglitz acknowledges, above, is that inheritance taxation may not
always be fair. Sociological theory engages with this. Theories of stratifi-
cation, for example, chart the evolution of what it means to be `fair', and
indeed what it means to be wealthy, so as to explain why taxes which were
587
152 id., at p. 162.
153 Harper, op. cit., n. 52, at p. 395.
154 J. Whalley, `Estate Duty as a ``Voluntary'' Tax; Evidence from Stamp Duty
Statistics' (1974) 84 Economic J. 638.
155 S. James, `Taxation Research as Economic Research' in M. Lamb, S. Lymer, J.
Freedman, and S. James, Taxation: An Interdisciplinary Approach to Research
(2005) 35±53, at 43.
156 J.E. Stiglitz, `Notes on Estate Taxes, Redistribution and the Concept of Balanced
Growth Path Incidence' (1978) 86 J. of Political Economics ss. 137±50.
157 id., at s. 139.
158 id.
159 id.
160 id.
161
`The changing awareness of what it means to be wealthy also demands a rethinking of
the sociological picture of social stratification.' S.M. Miller and A.J. Savoie, `Chal-
lenging Inequality/Challenging Sociology' (1999) 28 Contemporary Sociology 30, at 31.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
tolerated at one time now are disliked.
161
Thus, for example, in the United
Kingdom, allegations that the inheritance tax does not have an essential
fairness at its core have focused on the role played by the housing market in
the value of estates.
An illustration of this is provided by a book published by the Daily
Telegraph with the aim of helping its readers to avoid inheritance tax, which
warns that many families who would not consider themselves to be wealthy
are surprised to find that they are in fact affected, due to an unexpected rise
in the value of their family home.
162
This book implies that it is unfair that
families like these are affected by inheritance tax, and aims to help them to
avoid paying it.
163
The suggestion appears to be that whilst it is fair to expect
people who are popularly perceived as wealthy to pay some form of estate
tax, it is not fair to expect this of anyone else.
The availability of inheritance tax avoidance schemes, and the fact that
they may be too expensive for many taxpayers, contributes to this sense of
unfairness.
164
Braithwaite suggests that `[p]eople who see themselves as
poorer are less willing to pay tax voluntarily when people they perceive to be
richer are believed to cheat.'
165
Thus, the fact that trusts and other devices
that permit avoidance of inheritance tax come at a price undermines belief in
this tax, in that the `not really wealthy' taxpayer will suffer more keenly the
costs of purchasing an avoidance scheme.
166
Inheritance taxes present specific difficulties within analyses addressing
fairness, as they concern not only the taxpayer bequeathing the wealth, but
the beneficiary as well.
167
As Mirrlees writes:
[i]t seems to me that, just as gifts concern two people (at least), so taxes on
gifts and inheritance have double effects, being expenditure-related taxes from
the point of view of the giver, and lump-sum taxes (more or less) on the
receiver.
168
Any impact on overall economic efficiency, therefore, needs to take in to
account the effects on the behaviour of both the giver and the beneficiary.
169
Both also need to be seen as treated fairly.
Rising property prices, however, perhaps most of all have been the focus
588
162 M. Scott, How To Avoid Inheritance Tax (2006) 2, 3, 4, 7, 32.
163 id.
164 `The exemplar is Great Britain, whose estate taxes are both the most confiscatory
and the easiest to avoid ± a voluntary tax, according to one economist.' M.B. Levy,
`Liberal Equality and Inherited Wealth' (1983) 11 Political Theory 545±64, at 546.
165 Braithwaite, op. cit., n. 62, at p. 25.
166 Even a self-help book such as that published by the Daily Telegraph contains a
chapter title which warns: `Don't try this at home: why DIY won't work with IHT':
Scott, op. cit., n. 162, pp. 125±32.
167 J.A. Mirrlees, Welfare, Incentives and Taxation (2006) at 352.
168 id.
169 id.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
of recent debates on `fairness'.
170
Between (roughly) 1965 and 1989, home
ownership in the United Kingdom rose from approximately one-third to two-
thirds of the population.
171
This development is of great significance for both
the institution of the family and the economy, as many more families now
are in a position to bequeath something valuable to subsequent genera-
tions.
172
In many ways the family home has become the main focus of
inheritance taxation, for, as Harper explained, `most of us have little to
bequeath unless we own a house, but those of us who do potentially have
something of value to transmit to the next generation.'
173
There is a rich
literature analysing what might be described as the sociology of property
prices which might inform this discussion.
174
This literature acknowledges
the interactive impact of social values and perceptions on property prices,
but also recognizes the fact that home ownership plays an important role in
economic security, and simply, wealth.
175
This also might be considered, however, within the value of bequests to
the `conjugal family'.
176
Indeed, evidence suggests that Durkheim's
prediction that, as societies evolved, bequests increasingly would target
business organizations, as opposed to individual family members,
177
may
well come true. The average home-owner parent may hope to be able to
leave a valuable family home to his or her children, but there is a
concomitant development to the rise of family home ownership: longevity.
There is a chance that the parent will require expensive, long-term palliative
care in old age, which will consume the value of the home, and possibly
more.
178
The decision to liquidate the value of one's home to pay for care
589
170 See, generally, C. Hamnett, `The Geography of Housing Wealth and Inheritance in
Britain' (1992) 158 Geographical J. 307. In 1985, the top 10 per cent of households
in Britain had (after tax) incomes ten times greater than the bottom ten per cent: T.
Stark, A New A±Z of Income and Wealth (1988) at 9.
171 S. Harper, `Inheritance and Intergenerational Relationships' in Families in Ageing
Societies, ed. S. Harper (2004) 164±75, at 164.
172 id.
173 id., at p. 164.
174 See D.R. Harris, ```Property Values Drop When Blacks Move in, Because . . .'':
Racial and Socioeconomic Determinants of Neighborhood Desirability' (1999) 64
Am. Sociological Rev. 461; J.L. Bradach and R.G. Eccles, `Price, Authority, and
Trust: From Ideal Types to Plural Forms' (1989) 15 Annual Rev. of Sociology 97;
J.I. Gilderbloom and R.P. Appelbaum, `Toward a Sociology of Rent: Are Rental
Housing Markets Competitive?' (1987) 34 Social Problems 261.
175 See, generally, C. Hamnett, Winners and Losers: Home Ownership in Modern
Britain (1999). See, also, S. White, `Basic Capital' in The Civic Minimum: On the
Rights and Duties of Economic Citizenship (2003) 176±80, at 178. But compare F.
Thistlethwaite, `The Citadel and the Caravan: Anglo-American Relations in the
Twentieth Century' (1957) 9 Am. Q. 22, at 25±7.
176 Durkheim, op. cit., n. 100, at s. 232.
177 Schwartz, op. cit., n. 101.
178 Harper, op. cit., n. 171, at p. 165 explains that `the specific issue of using assets to
fund care in old age is rather new to social policy' and is thus rather under-studied.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
possibly will not even be that of the `home-owner parent', but will fall to
adult children. In fact, the parent's own potential longevity, and not the
taxman, may pose the greatest risk to inheritance.
179
What might be described as the `fairness' debate in inheritance taxation
also tends to focus on the suggestion that inheritance tax is unfair because it
involves a form of `double taxation,' particularly where the family home is
concerned.
180
The complaint is that tax on the family home already has been
paid by parents, thus, it is unfair to ask their children to pay yet more tax on
it after their death. Double taxation arguments
181
seem to focus less on
questions of timing, however, than on the troubles of taxpayers with estates
that are increasingly dwindling due to tax. It is the perceived, devastating
impact of this tax on middle-class taxpayers, in particular, however, that has
most fuelled current political discourse.
182
Additionally, the government's
reluctance to send clear signals to the middle classes as to its plans for
inheritance tax ± as with the failure to mention IHT reform in the Pre-Budget
Report 2006, discussed above ± has increased criticism. This is significant,
because psychologists have suggested that if tax collection agencies behave
as if they trust taxpayers, then taxpayers are more likely to behave in a
`trustworthy' manner.
183
This explains, Chorvat argues, why enforcement
can sometimes decrease pre-existing compliance behaviour,
184
and also
suggests that any indication that the government is not `playing fairly' can be
detrimental to its acceptance of a tax.
If inheritance taxation is unfair, then avoiding it is unproblematic, at least
from a moral standpoint.
185
Unlike a waiter not declaring his tips, however,
it can be very expensive to avoid inheritance tax, given the cost of avoidance
schemes. Thus, the tax appears even more unjust, as the wealthy would
590
179 See, generally, J. Huber and P. Skidmore, New Old: Why the Baby Boomers Won't
Be Pensioned Off (2003).
180 This is part of the US-centric, early-twentieth-century debate that requires updating.
For an early example of this sort of analysis (very much rooted in the theories of J.S.
Mill), see I. Fisher, `The Double Taxation of Savings' (1939) 29 Am. Economic Rev.
16.
181 Which must be treated fairly, given the relief afforded to homeowners for capital
gains.
182 See Scott, op. cit., n. 162.
183 T. Chorvat, `Trust and Taxation' in McCaffery and Slemrod, op. cit., n. 151, at p.
222, citing L. Feld and B. Frey, `Trust Breeds Trust: How Taxpayers are Treated'
(2002) 3(2) Economics of Governance 87±100. As Chorvat has stressed, `[t]o the
extent that this is an accurate depiction of the relationship, it is an implicit contract
and therefore difficult to precisely define its terms. One important point about such
contracts is that they can only be created by prior conduct. Therefore, large-scale
changes in the behavior of one of the parties can be viewed as a violation of the
contract' (emphasis added).
184 id.
185 For a discussion of this, see H. Cremer and P. Pestieau, `Wealth Transfer Taxation:
ASurvey' (2003) at arp.lse.ac.uk/PapersDB/Cremer-Pestieau_
(CESifo1061).pdf >.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
appear to have the ability, even the right, to avoid it.
186
Although it might
appear to be an obvious point, it is important to appreciate the differences
between taxpayers in the inheritance tax debate.
187
For example, are parents bequeathing the family home to adult children so
that they will not have to struggle to `get on the property ladder,' as perhaps
they did? Then, the discourse could focus on affordable housing, and the
relative value of home ownership. Early-twentieth-century debates on
helping `the poor man' through inheritance taxation
188
must confront the `No
Exit Obligation,'
189
which presents a primary claim on the attention of
parents, even of adult children. Thus, confusion about the language of
inheritance taxation may be dismissed, perhaps, in favour of analyses
capable of convincing a wider populace that such taxes are economically
efficient, progressive, and indeed, fair.
CONCLUSION
A revival of the discourse of inheritance taxation, grounded in sociological
theory, could help to explain why the tax is fair, and it should not be avoided.
Durkheim's and Marx's criticisms of inherited property are potentially very
useful, but it is perhaps Beckert's description of the bequeathing of property
as an economic act that holds the most promise.
190
If understood and
discussed as an economic act, then perhaps inheritance tax may be salvaged
from the emotional debate of family homes, and legacies, which currently
threatens it. This is not to suggest that the emotion of inheritance should be
entirely disregarded, and indeed Durkheim's analyses demonstrate the
importance of societal attachment to property.
191
Rather, a post-functionalist
analysis of, for example, the motive behind the economic act of bequests
192
may serve to spark debate in a productive way.
Broome has analysed the importance of a good death, suggesting that `[i]t
seems plausible that a good end to life is more valuable than, say, a good
591
186 Green presents a perhaps idyllic definition of tax avoidance: `[t]ax avoidance seems
to involve an amoral act ± neither superogatory nor fraudulent; in its most negative
light, it is mildly exploitative or selfish.' S.P. Green, Lying, Cheating and Stealing:
A Moral Theory of White-Collar Crime (2006) 243±4.
187 N. Taylor, `Understanding Taxpayer Attitudes Through Understanding Taxpayer
Identities' in Taxing Democracy, ed. V. Braithwaite (2003) 71±92, at 89. As Adams
suggested, `[e]vasion can be prevented just so long as men feel it cheaper to employ
the state to superintend the distribution of their property after death than to employ
private agencies.' Adams, op. cit., n. 147, at p. 242.
188 Seligman, op. cit., n. 68, at p. 229.
189 Alstott, op. cit., n. 119.
190 Beckert, op. cit., n. 105, at p. 367.
191 Cotterrell, op. cit., n. 111, at p. 134.
192 Kohli, op. cit., n. 114, at p. 268.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
middle life.'
193
This desire perhaps explains much of the inheritance tax
debate. It is evident in the language used to describe inheritance taxation,
and in the conflicts that arise over the legal treatment of adult children.
This article concludes that sociologists and tax legal theorists need to
revive the discourse of inheritance tax law in the United Kingdom. Por-
trayals of inheritance taxation as an attempt to take away all that a family has
achieved financially may present political challenges, but the accusations
may be answered. Indeed, the objective of an inheritance tax need not be
absolute wealth redistribution, or even wholly aspirational. As White
explains, `[i]n its non-ideal form, fair reciprocity does not require that we
eliminate all significant brute luck disadvantage.'
194
This does not, however,
relieve us of the obligation to address, for example, racial and class
inequality, which are thought to be perpetuated through the ongoing process
of intergenerational wealth transfers.
195
Given that White suggests that
permitting significant levels of inheritance can impede social cohesion, and
increase the gap of mutual understanding between those who must work for a
living, and those who do not,
196
this is an important task.
`No economist'
197
may doubt the value of inheritance taxes, but taxpayers
have complained bitterly, and frequently, over the past ten years in both the
United States and the United Kingdom. In 2007, after thirty years of what
Bartels described as a `massive social experiment'
198
regarding economic
inequality, the terms of discussion have become intensely politicized and, as
a burgeoning literature is beginning to suggest, the capacity for reasoned
public discourse about taxation is, as a consequence, diminishing.
199
In the United Kingdom, it need not stay that way. Of course, the modern
uproar was not easily predictable. Carrington may have presumed that
`civilized nations' accept some form of wealth redistribution upon death as a
given.
200
This presumption may not have stood the test of time, but it need
not follow that the discourse is incapable of being revived.
The fortunes of inheritance taxation and property values may be deeply
intertwined in the United Kingdom, and hint at the possibility that
inheritance taxation in some ways is viewed as an assault on the family.
201
In this context, arguments might be refined to suggest that, for example,
people who, thanks to inheriting the value of their parents' home, do not
need to struggle to pull together the down payment which enables them to
592
193 J. Broome, Weighing Lives (2004) at 227.
194 White, op. cit., n. 175, at p. 179.
195 id.
196 id.
197 Baldwin, op. cit., n. 1, p. 1.
198 Bartels, op. cit., n. 3, at p. 15, citing R.J. Samuelson, `Indifferent to Inequality?'
Newsweek May 2007.
199 See id., and Graetz and Shapiro, op. cit., n. 9.
200 Carrington, op. cit., n. 26, p. 568.
201 id.
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School
embark on the property ladder, also may have difficulty understanding
people who are not so fortunate. Sociological theory may inform this
discourse. At least, it may help to explain that, simply because wealth
emanates from the value of a family home, it does not make it something
other than wealth. Indeed, simply because the value of what previous
generations (even very recently) may have described as an average house
(especially in the south east of England) may have soared in value, does not
negate the significance of that value.
593
ß2007 The Author. Journal Compilation ß2007 Cardiff University Law School

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT